Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-wq2xx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-17T02:06:02.930Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Plantinga's Case Against Naturalistic Epistemology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Evan Fales*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of Iowa

Abstract

In Warrant and Proper Function, Alvin Plantinga claims that metaphysical naturalism, when joined to a naturalized epistemology, is self-undermining. Plantinga argues that naturalists are committed to a neoDarwinian account of our origins, and that the reliability of our cognitive faculties is improbable or unknown relative to that theory. If the theory is true, then we are in no position to know that, whereas theism, if true, underwrites cognitive reliability. I seek to turn the tables on Plantinga, showing that neoDarwinism provides strong reasons for expecting general cognitive reliability, whereas the likelihood of that relative to theism is unknowable.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1996

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

Send reprint requests to the author, Department of Philosophy, University of Iowa, Iowa City, IA 52242.

References

Darwin, C. (1919), The Life and Letters of Charles Darwin, Vol. I. New York: D. Appleton & Co.Google Scholar
Fales, E. (1990), Causation and Universais. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Fales, E. (1994), “Review of Alvin Plantinga, Warrant and Proper Function”, Mind 103: 391395.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fales, E. (forthcoming a), “Mystical Experience as Evidence”, International Journal for Philosphy of Religion.Google Scholar
Fales, E. (forthcoming b), “Scientific Explanations of Mystical Experience, Parts I and II”, Religious Studies.Google Scholar
Fales, E. and Wasserman, E. A. (1992), “Causal Knowledge: What Can Psychology Teach Philosophers?”, The Journal of Mind and Behavior 13: 127.Google Scholar
Flanagan, O. (1992), Consciousness Reconsidered. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Kahneman, D., Slovic, P., and Tversky, A. (eds.), (1982), Judgment Under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Milton, K. (1993), “Diet and Primate Evolution”, Scientific American 269: 8693.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Nisbett, R. E. and Ross, L. (1980), Human Inference: Strategies, and Shortcomings of Social Judgment. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Plantinga, A. (1985), “Self-Profile”, in Tomberlin, J. E. and Van Inwagen, P. (eds.), Alvin Plantinga. Boston: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Plantinga, A. (1991), “When Faith and Reason Clash: Evolution and the Bible”, Christian Scholars Review 21: 832 and 81109.Google Scholar
Plantinga, A. (1993), Warrant and Proper Function. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plantinga, A. (unpublished), “Nature Defeated”.Google Scholar
Shanks, H., Dever, W., Halpern, B. and McCarter, P. K., Jr. (1992), The Rise of Ancient Israel Washington, D.C.: Biblical Archaeology Society.Google Scholar
Stich, S. (1990), The Fragmentation of Reason. Cambridge, MA.: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Van Gulick, R. (1994), “Deficit Studies and the Function of Phenomenal Consciousness”, in Graham, G. and Stephens, G. L. (eds.), Philosophical Psychopathology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Velmans, M. (1991), “Is Human Information Processing Conscious?”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14: 651669.CrossRefGoogle Scholar